QR6.1.8 Neutral Monism

Chalmer’s last option is neutral monism, that something more primal than matter or mind is the cause of both, as suggested by Russell in 1921:

“The stuff of which the world of our experience is composed is, in my belief, neither mind nor matter, but something more primitive than either. Both mind and matter seem to be composite, and the stuff of which they are compounded lies in a sense between the two, in a sense above them both, like a common ancestor.” (Russell, 2005)

Russell didn’t specify a common ancestor for mind and matter, but if quantum reality creates the observer as well as physical events, quantum realism is a neutral monism as Russell proposed.

Consider the premise that every physical event must have an observer. Virtual worlds exist by being observed so if our physical reality is virtual, it should be the same. Quantum theory confirms that physical events require observation, as spreading quantum waves only collapse to a physical event when observed. It follows that an observer is needed for physical events to occur.

We also know that our universe began at a moment in time so without observation, it would have stayed in a quantum superposition. The initial physical events had to be observed to occur. If our universe began as a light plasma that physically collided into basic matter (Chapter 3), the only entities that could observe were photons. The simplest conclusion that lets observation cause the initial physical events is that photons observed.

It isn’t claimed that photons observe as we do, but that they observe quantum scale events of 10-35 meters and 10-43 seconds. Such events are incredibly short and brief to us, as they occur more times per second than there have been seconds in our universe. That photons observe seems preposterous but the alternative, that only we observe the universe, is equally so.

To observe so little so briefly seems hardly worth it to us, but smallism, that facts about big things come from facts about small things (Coleman, 2006), can apply to observation too. If the observer experience began small, like everything else, then macro-consciousness can derive from micro-consciousness (Chalmers, 1996) (p305). It is possible that photons observe, so who are we to say that they don’t when we claim that we do? By Conway’s free will theorem, either everything is conscious or nothing is (Koch, 2014), so it is simpler to say that observation always existed than to explain how it began with no precedent.

If observation existed from the start, then photons observe on their scale, but not as we do. To avoid confusion, let us call quantum-scale observations proto-consciousness, as Penrose proposed in 1944 (Penrose, 1994), and more recently:

… the elements of proto-consciousness would be intimately tied in with the most primitive Planck level ingredients of space-time geometry, these presumed ‘ingredients’ being taken to be at the absurdly tiny level of 10-35m and 10-43s, a distance and time some 20 orders of magnitude smaller than those of normal particle-physics scales and their most rapid processes.(Penrose & Hameroff, 2017) p21.

That consciousness began small answers another question, that if everything is a player in our virtual universe, isn’t it boring for some? If one asked for players in a virtual universe like ours, who wants to be a rock on mars, that just sits there for a million years? But a rock is an aggregate of molecules, so it observes on a molecular scale, not a rock scale. On this scale, something new happens every nanosecond, so it isn’t boring at all.

This isn’t panpsychism, that matter is conscious, because in quantum realism, matter doesn’t exist except as a view. Panpsychism assumes that matter exists to have a consciousness property, but if matter itself doesn’t exist, it can’t have that property. This is possible because previous chapters derived matter properties, like mass, charge, and spin, from quantum reality.

Quantum realism changes the question from how dead matter became able to observe to how proto-observations became human observations. It replaces the explanatory gap between matter and consciousness with an evolutionary gap, between what atoms observe and what we do. The conclusion, developed later, is that the ability to observe had to exist from the beginning to cause physical events. Hence, instead of asking how matter acquired consciousness, we now ask how matter observations evolved, which raises the question of how brains evolved?

Next

QR6.1.7 Cognitive Theories

We assume realism when we observe that a reality exists out there apart from us. Physical realism calls it physical and quantum realism calls it quantum but, in both cases, sensory events cause nerves to cause observation. If sensory events cause nerve events that cause mental events, one can short-circuit the sequence to argue that mind alone creates observations. This goes against realism, but it is still logical.

Solipsism for example claims that mind alone creates reality, as it does when we dream. This theory is impossible to disprove but it isn’t accepted by science because it predicts nothing new and doesn’t explain how a mind that can dream arose in the first place.

QBism is a theory of physics that uses this “mind-trick” to dismiss not physical reality, as solipsism does, but quantum reality. It argues that quantum probabilities are degrees of belief about physical outcomes, so quantum waves are just in the mind. Like solipsism, it is impossible to disprove, as one could say gravity is a belief about how matter moves, so it is in the mind too. QBism doesn’t do this, as it uses the mind argument selectively to deny quantum reality not physical reality. Like solipsism, QBism has no scientific value because it makes no predictions nor does it explain how a mind with beliefs can exist (McQueen, 2017). That physicists now invoke the mind to deny quantum reality is telling, because the elephant in the room is that quantum causes can explain what physical causes can’t.

Another cognitive theory of consciousness attributes the mind to complexity, by claiming that brains become conscious in the same way that ants form colonies, because:

“… ant colonies are no different from brains in many respects.” (Hofstadter & Dennett, 1981) p181.

The brain is then just a colony of nerves that communicate electrically instead of chemically, as ants do. By this logic, the chemical trails ants lay down are the colony’s “language” just as neuron wiring causes our language. Dumb neurons then create consciousness as dumb ants create a colony, so it remains as neurons come and go, just as a colony remains as ants come and go. Crick’s “pack of neurons” theory is now that we are nothing but a colony of nerves.

The evidence that ant colonies are conscious is weak, as if an ant colony is a being that can communicate, why haven’t we learned its language by now, as we did that of the bees? It doesn’t help to suggest the same logic applies to countries like Russia or America:

“… let us think a bit right now about whether it makes sense to think of ‘being’ a country. Does a country have thoughts or beliefs?” (Hofstadter & Dennett, 1981) p192

To say that consciousness is private so countries might be conscious is just a smoke-screen, as no evidence at all suggests that countries are beings. Scientists don’t ask others to disprove their speculations but go where the evidence leads. To argue that what appears as a unity might be a being is an appeal to naivety. If that were true, tornadoes might be conscious beings, but they aren’t, and neither are ant colonies or countries. When we connect physical parts into a bicycle, it becomes an entity to us but not to itself.

After presenting paradoxical Gestalt patterns and speculating that ant colonies are conscious, the underwhelming conclusion of this theory is that:

“Mind is a pattern perceived by a mind.” (Hofstadter & Dennett, 1981) p200.

It isn’t hard to see that this statement is circular, because a mind is assumed to perceive a pattern that is then equated to the mind that perceived it. This theory, that mind is a creation of mind, is just another miracle thrown up to maintain physical realism.

Next

QR6.1.6 Information Theories

Physical reality can’t explain consciousness but its information derivative is claimed to do so. Integrated information theory argues that “consciousness is integrated information(Tononi, 2008), generalizing an earlier theory that brain functions like language, vision and hearing deposit information into a global workspace that causes consciousness (Baars, 1988).

Distant brain regions process sight, sound, touch, and smell, then pass the results to areas specializing in memory, emotions, language, planning, and motor responses, but how are global decisions made? Global workspace theory claims that sensory results are put into a common area, for higher functions like memory or language to use. Consciousness then arises when:

“… the information has entered into a specific storage area that makes it available to the rest of the brain.” (Dehaene, 2014) p163.

Yet if a specific brain area is critical for consciousness, why hasn’t it been found? Workspace theory also suggests that neurons “chat” like little people:

“… neural systems do not merely report to their superiors; they also chat among themselves.”(Dehaene, 2014) p176.

Brain science then reduces to neuron sociology (Nunez, 2016) p18, by the analogy of crowd control on the Internet:

“… it is helpful to think metaphorically of a theater of mind. In the conscious spotlight on stage – the global workspace – an actor speaks, and his words and gestures are distributed to many unconscious audience members, sitting in the darkened hall. Different listeners understand the performance in different ways. But as the audience claps or boos in response, the actor can change his words, or walk off to yield to the next performer.(Baars & Laureys, 2004) p672.

Such analogies are seductive, but that neural areas chat like little people over nerve phone lines, or clap and boo each other as we do online, contradicts information theory. To exchange data like this, the brain would need common protocols, just as the Internet needs these protocol layers to share information:

a. Data. Ethernet protocol.

b. Network. Internet protocol (IP).

c.  Transport. Transmission Control Program protocol (TCP).

d. Application. Hyper Text Transfer Protocol (http).

The Internet’s TCP/IP/http protocols took decades to develop from the original Arpanet, and it was done by a central group the brain just doesn’t have. Browsers then need to be updated to work with upgrades, like from IP version 4 to 6, but the brain has no way to do this. And these protocols are just to transmit data packages – to actually see a picture or hear music still needs an application specialized for that data type!

For example, Notepad displays text and Paint displays pictures but loading text into Paint or a picture into Notepad gives nonsense, so even if data was put into a common area, neither could read what the other posted. To do this, Paint would need code to analyze text and Notepad would need code to analyze pictures, which increases program size. And if either application changed the other would have to update its included code to work reliably.

Programs like Word that display text and pictures become huge as a result, and they still can’t read zip files, for example. For every brain function to include every other denies the benefits of specialization and updating every area when one changes to share data isn’t feasible for the brain. Information science tells us that one can’t plug the optic nerve into the auditory cortex and expect information to flow like water.

The auditory area of the brain can no more read smell data than I can read a text in Chinese, so what use is a common stage if neural actors don’t use the same language? A global workspace would need a global translator of smells, thoughts, movements, and feelings, which is impossible.

Finally, the Internet shares data so shouldn’t it become conscious? Information integration theorists expect it to do so soon (Koch, 2014), despite no evidence at all for this.

Theories of brain data exchange must respect information science, but global workspace theory doesn’t, and what won’t work for computer networks won’t work for brains either. The cartoonish concept of neural areas as little people chatting via a common brain language that isn’t possible, merging claps or boos they can’t make, on a central stage that doesn’t exist, is a fantasy. The brain needs some other way for different regions to share information.

Next

QR6.1.5 Dualism

In 1637, Descartes argued that scientific physicalism and religious idealism are both true, because mind was a substance outside space just as matter was a substance within it. However, two centuries later, Laplace rejected this, arguing that matter alone determined the universe:

We may regard the present state of the universe as the effect of its past and the cause of its future. An intellect which at a certain moment would know all forces that set nature in motion, and all positions of all items of which nature is composed, if this intellect were also vast enough to submit these data to analysis, it would embrace in a single formula the movements of the greatest bodies of the universe and those of the tiniest atom; for such an intellect nothing would be uncertain and the future just like the past would be present before its eyes.” Laplace, in (Truscott & Emory, 1951) p4.

That physical laws explained everything challenged mind-matter dualism by claiming that science not only didn’t need religion, it was better off without it. The case was that all physical events have a physical cause, so the universe is causally closed. It is a causal chain with no gaps, like a tube of balls, where pushing one end makes a ball pop out the other end, with no mind or soul needed to make it happen. If all physical facts come from other physical facts, there is no room for mental causes. Causal closure implies that if mind has a physical cause, it is also physical and so not mind, and if not, it can’t have a physical effect (Kim, 1999). Causal closure implies that a non-physical mind can’t affect physical events.

Supporters of dualism sought to demonstrate non-physical causes by paranormal events, like the ability to mentally move objects (telekinesis) or see the unseeable (extra-sensory perception), but attempts to replicate mental powers haven’t been definitive (Kelly at al., 2007).

Then just as physicalism was replacing dualism, a new theory, quantum mechanics, concluded that no physical event is 100% certain. In the Stern-Gerlach experiment, silver atoms in a magnetic field go up or down based on a spin that is perfectly random. We can’t pre-sort the atoms into those going up or down because they are initially identical, and the spin that moves them up or down in the magnetic field is decided when they observe it, not before. Quantum theory says this happens when the atoms are in the field, just as where a photon hits a screen is decided at the screen. In a mechanical universe, the physical past should entirely define the physical future, but it isn’t so in our universe.

   When quantum entities interact, they choose their physical future from what is possible and this unpredictability is part of our universe. Quantum theory rejects the idea that the universe is completely physically predictable, and the evidence agrees, so it can’t be a big machine. 

In quantum theory, when a quantum wave is observed, it randomly actualizes a physical event from one of its lawful possibilities and obliterates the rest. This stops the quantum wave expanding endlessly by restarting it. An observer outside the quantum system ends the chain of quantum events, but there is by definition nothing outside a closed physical universe to do this.

  An endless physical chain with no gaps has no way to select one link to be an observation, so it has no way to allow observation or choice. In contrast quantum realism accepts both because it accepts quantum theory entirely. Figure 6.2 compares the reality options.

Figure 6.2 compares the reality options:

a. In physical realism, a series of physical events (P) lawfully cause each other with no gaps, so there is no observation or choice.

b. In dualism, a series of physical events (P) and mental events (M) affect physical events, so there is observation and choice.

c.  In quantum realism, quantum events (Q) cause observations (O) of physical events (P), so there is both observation and choice. Note that many quantum events produce one physical event.  

In Figure 6.2a, each set of physical events causes the next, with no choice or observation possible, so there can be no evolution or observation, yet we know that both occur.

In Figure 6.2b, two causal chains, mental (M) and physical (P), affect not only their realm but also the other, but that mind events cause physical events is both unproven and illogical.

In Figure 6.2c, physical reality (P) arises when quantum waves (Q) interact to allow observation (O), as quantum theory says. Every quantum collapse is then an observation choice.

If quantum waves spread, interact and collapse to give the observations we call the physical world. Quantum realism has no gaps for physical causes just as physical realism had no gaps for mental causes. A physical event is an observed result, not a cause, so it causes nothing. In this view, physical reality is an epiphenomenon that, like a train whistle, appears but doesn’t affect the quantum engine driving reality.

  If quantum reality creates physical reality, physical laws derive entirely from quantum laws. Physical causality is based on quantum causality, so it is correlation not causality. When a quantum entity picks a physical event from the possibilities it has discovered, it redefines the future timeline. Quantum theory works when physical realism doesn’t because it recognizes that quantum events cause the future, not physical events.

Next

QR6.1.4 Physical Realism

The best theory to explain consciousness should be the one that also best explains matter. This is widely thought to be physical realism because the equations of physics predict how matter behaves, but to do so they routinely invoke non-physical causes, like quantum waves.

Consider the question, is matter a particle or a wave? Electrons were first seen as particles with mass, charge, and spin, until they were found to be dimensionless points, so how can a particle of no size have mass or charge? How can a particle with no physical extent spin? No-one really knows, so it’s a miracle.

Physics then described electrons as waves to explain their behavior in atoms, but physical waves vibrate in physical space while the Dirac wave function vibrates electrons in an imaginary plane outside our space. No-one knows how an electron wave can vibrate outside physical space, so it’s another miracle.

Both views sometimes work, so matter is said to be sometimes a wave and sometimes a particle. This wave-particle duality is accepted although particles aren’t wave-like nor are waves particle-like. No-one can say how an electron knows to be a particle in space but a wave in an atom, so its yet another miracle.

If a miracle is an outcome with no physical basis, physics needs a lot of them to explain the physical world in physical terms, for as Part I established:

       Gravity has to be attributed to graviton particles that have no physical basis at all.

       Light travels at a constant speed with no physical reason to go at just that speed.

       Moving matter changes space and time but has no physical way to do so.

       The vacuum of empty space exerts a pressure that has no physical basis.

       An electron can suddenly appear outside a Gaussian sphere with no physical path.

       An object on a path can be detected without any physical contact at all.

       The physical universe is said to have created itself from nothing, which isn’t physical.

       Entangled photons define each other faster than the physical speed of light.

       Most of our galaxy consists of dark matter that has no physical explanation.

       Most of the universe consists of dark energy that has no physical explanation.

       Our universe consists of matter not anti-matter for no known physical reason.

       Quantum waves that aren’t physical predict physical event probabilities.

How can a theory based on miracles call itself realistic? Is it realistic that imaginary waves cause physical events? Is it realistic that virtual particles cause real forces? Is it realistic that particles with no size spin? Is it realistic that massless gluons create most of a proton’s mass? Is it realistic that the future affects the past in delayed-choice experiments? Is it realistic that objects can be detected without physical touching? Physical realism has produced what some now call fairytale physics (Baggot, 2013), that predicts what can’t be verified and can’t explain what can.

Physical realism doesn’t deliver but is accepted because the only alternative is thought to be medieval superstition. Physics prefers its new fairytale to the old one, but science shouldn’t be about fairytales at all. The fault isn’t the equations, because they work, but the fantasy that materialism has spun around them.

Physical realism survives because physicists think that science needs it and scientists think that physics needs it, yet neither is actually true:

a. Physicists think that science requires physical causes, but science verifies theories by physical results not causes, and physical realism is just a theory of science.

b.  Scientists think that physics requires physical causes, but this isn’t true either as quantum science predicts physical events from non-physical quantum waves.

The laws of physics work just as well if the quantum world is real, because realism still applies. Neither physics nor science needs physical realism, as the following story illustrates:

A father and son would meet to discuss the meaning of life over a meal. Each time they were joined by a third man who ate most of the food, dominated the conversation and left when the bill arrived so he paid nothing. One day the son said “Your friend eats a lot and never pays!” to which the father replied “He’s not my friend, I thought he was yours!”.

The third man was accepted by father and son because both thought he was the other’s friend. Likewise, physical realism helps neither physics nor science, so both are better off without it. It is an impostor that pontificates but doesn’t deliver when the reality check arrives.

Next

QR6.1.3 Current Theories

The scientific approach to a fact is to explain it, not to ignore or dismiss it, so if consciousness is a valid subject for science, the question raised is:

“Why does conscious experience exist?” (Chalmers, 1996) (p5)

Those who argue that the universe is a machine so consciousness can’t exist must also agree that they are also machines, so why should we listen to them? A detailed review of theories on consciousness divides them exhaustively into six categories A-F (Chalmers, 2003):

A.  Materialism-A. Consciousness doesn’t exist except as an imagined effect of the physical brain (Dennett, 1991). If physical causes explain everything, there is nothing beyond the physical brain that needs explaining, so the hard problem doesn’t exist.

B.  Materialism-B. Consciousness exists but is identical to certain physical brain states for all practical purposes (Block & Stalnaker, 1999). If consciousness equates to physical states, the hard problem is solved.

C.  Materialism-C. Consciousness exists but is a physical derivative of the brain in theory (Nagel, 1974) (Edelman, 2003). If physical causes explain everything, they will one day explain consciousness so the hard problem will be solved, eventually.

Theories A-C argue that consciousness arises from a physical process because physical realism is correct. Yet it isn’t easy to argue that the observer experience is imaginary (A) or that it equates to matter states (B), so most believers in physical realism are left hoping that a miracle will one-day derive consciousness from matter.

D. Dualism-D. Consciousness exists by itself to affect physical events and matter in turn affects consciousness (Stapp, 1993). If consciousness exists as well as matter, the hard problem is solved.

E.  Dualism-E. Consciousness is a brain by-product that helps survival but doesn’t affect physical reality (Zizzi, 2003). If consciousness is an epiphenomenon of physical activity, the hard problem is solved.

F.   Neutral Monism-F. If both consciousness and matter derive from a primal cause that is neither, then matter doesn’t need to cause consciousness and the hard problem is solved.

Theories D-F argue that consciousness is a non-physical reality. Dualism-D lets it affect matter from a non-physical realm, Dualism-E lets it exist but have no effect on matter, and neutral monism-F sees both consciousness and matter as derivative, but as Chalmers notes:

No-one has yet developed any sort of detailed theory in this class, and it is not yet clear whether such a theory can be developed.(Chalmers, 2003)

Quantum realism is therefore a neutral monism but first, we review physical realism.

QR6.1.2 The First Fact

The ability to observe refers to the phenomenon of consciousness not a brain function (Block, 1995), so it doesn’t require any sense, thought or feeling. Damage to the visual cortex causes blindness but doesn’t stop consciousness, as people with locked in syndrome are still conscious. People born with no cortex are conscious (Merker, 2007) so it can’t depend on a cortical area. No brain area has been identified as the seat of consciousness, because it can persist even when the cerebellum, amygdala, hippocampi or cortex fail. The ability to observe is just there in a way that doesn’t require any particular brain function. It can apply to any sense, memory or feeling, so James concluded in 1892 that consciousness is a fundamental fact:

The first and foremost concrete fact which everyone will affirm to belongs to his inner experience is the fact that consciousness of some sort goes on.” (James, 2019)

In scientific terms, this fact is valid because anyone can confirm that they observe and it is reliable because others can repeat the experience. That we each observe differently is irrelevant to the fact that we do observe. Without an observer there is no first person, so we would say “It is red” not “I see red”. To say I see or I hear implies an observer.

We know that we observe phenomena but we assume that it really exists (Kant, 2002). I know that I observe but I assume a physical world out there. I know with absolute certainty that I observe, but everything else is just an assumption, or as science says, a theory.

     In physics, both relativity and quantum theory need an observer, one to provide the observer reference frame and the other to trigger a quantum collapse. Science is based on observation, so it is no surprise that the ability to observe is fundamental, as every fact depends on it. In our lives, and in science, the first fact is that we observe because without it, no other facts are possible.

Next

QR6.1.1 The Hard Problem

Are you one or many? Most people call themselves I not we, but if “I” refers to the body, it is a collective of cells that constantly die and are replaced. Skin loses about a million cells a day and it is just one organ. Red blood cells live maybe four months, white blood cells a year or so, skin cells a few weeks and colon cells a few days. Where is the “I” in a bunch of cells that come and go? That some nerves may last a lifetime led one biologist to conclude that I am my nerves:

“The Astonishing Hypothesis is that ‘You’, your joys and your sorrows, your memories and your ambitions, your sense of identity and free will, are in fact no more than the behavior of a vast assembly of nerve cells and their associated molecules. As Lewis Carroll’s Alice might have phrased it: ‘You’re nothing but a pack of neurons’.” (Crick, 1995)

If so, should I call myself We? If “I” is a medieval error, like that the earth is flat, should we now say We did this instead of I did it? If you don’t want to refer to yourself “We”, then welcome to the hard problem of consciousness (Chalmers, 1996), that we experience life as a single “I” even though we are physically a collection of cells.

Neurons respond to one light frequency as “red” and another as “blue” but why is red this experience and blue that one? Nothing in neuroscience requires the processing of different light frequencies to give experiences, so what causes redness and blueness? The hard problem is that we don’t know why sensory input creates an experience as well as a response.

Imagine a scientist who knew all the facts there are to know about blue from a monochrome screen, such as how neurons analyze blue light frequencies (Jackson, 1982). Yet if she then sees blue for the first time, it’s a new experience, so what does she now know that she didn’t before? The hard problem is that the facts of blueness don’t explain the experience of seeing blue.

The Islamic scientist Avicenna proposed a thought experiment: a man floating in a void with no body sensations at all has no awareness of his arms, legs, heart or any other body part but still knows he exists. The floating man knows I am, even if all inputs stop. The hard problem is that the observer remains even when nothing is being observed.

We consider ourselves conscious, and so divide reality into beings that are conscious like us and matter that isn’t, but where is the line between? If people are conscious, are dogs, or insects or plants? If I am conscious, is the baby, fetus, or the one cell I grew from also conscious? Dividing reality like this gives an explanatory gap between the matter that makes our body and our experience of it (Levine, 1983). I observe a room of matter but if I am in the room, am I also matter? If what applies to matter also applies to me, am I also a thing?

Conway’s free will theorem is that the same rules apply to everything, so either everything is conscious or nothing is (Conway & Koch, 2006). If we are conscious, so is matter, and if matter isn’t, then neither are we. That we are conscious but the universe we came from isn’t, is illogical. The hard problem is that no property of matter predicts the observer experience we report.

After centuries of discussion, the hard problem today is no easier than it ever was:

The question of how matter gives rise to felt experience is one of the most vexing problems we know of. (Brooks, 2020)

Science still can’t explain how we can experience physical events in a body made of matter.

Next

QR6.1 What Is Consciousness?

One must define a topic to study it but scientists don’t agree on what consciousness is. Some say it doesn’t exist, some say it causes everything, while others are in-between. Let us define consciousness as the ability to observe and experience a physical event, not just respond to input as a camera might do. 

QR6.1.1 The Hard Problem

QR6.1.2 The First Fact

QR6.1.3 Current Theories

QR6.1.4 Physical Realism

QR6.1.5 Dualism

QR6.1.6 Information Theories

QR6.1.7 Cognitive Theories

QR6.1.8 Neutral Monism

Next

Chapter 6

Quantum Realism Part II: The Observer Reality

CHAPTER 6. THE MYSTERY OF CONSCIOUSNESS

Brian Whitworth, New Zealand

I regard consciousness as fundamental. I regard matter as derivative from consciousness. We cannot get behind consciousness. Everything that we talk about, everything that we regard as existing, postulates consciousness.   Max Planck (Sullivan, 1931)

Figure 6.1 A virtual reality emerges as quantum reality observes itself

Download Whole Chapter

    Quantum realism is the theory that quantum reality exists and it creates the physical universe as a virtual reality by interacting with itself (Figure 6.1). While previous chapters explained the observed in quantum terms, this chapter addresses the conscious observer. Consciousness is a mystery because nothing in the physical universe explains how we observe. No law of physics requires matter to observe at all and smartphones and driverless cars make complex choices without an “I” experience, so why don’t we? The mystery of consciousness is that a purely physical universe doesn’t imply or even allow the observer experience that we all report having.

QR6.1 What Is Consciousness?

QR6.2 Evolving A Brain

QR6.3 Evolving Consciousness

QR6.4 Discussion Questions

QR6.5 References

Next